Preamble
| What
Are American Values? | What
about God? | A
Just War? | Conclusion
| Original
Signatories | Endnotes
|
Preamble
AT TIMES it becomes necessary for a nation to defend
itself through force of arms. Because war is a grave matter,
involving the sacrifice and taking of precious human life,
conscience demands that those who would wage the war state clearly
the moral reasoning behind their actions, in order to make plain to
one another, and to the world community, the principles they are
defending.
We affirm five fundamental truths that pertain to all people
without distinction:
1. All human
beings are born free and equal in dignity and rights.
2. The basic
subject of society is the human person, and the legitimate
role of government is to protect and help to foster the
conditions for human flourishing.
3. Human
beings naturally desire to seek the truth about life's purpose
and ultimate ends.
4. Freedom of conscience and religious
freedom are inviolable rights of the human person.
5. Killing
in the name of God is contrary to faith in God and is the
greatest betrayal of the universality of religious faith.
We fight to defend ourselves and to defend these universal
principles.
[Back
to Top]
What are American
Values?
SINCE SEPTEMBER 11, millions of Americans have asked
themselves and one another, why? Why are we the targets of these
hateful attacks? Why do those who would kill us, want to kill
us?
We recognize that at times our nation has acted with arrogance
and ignorance toward other societies. At times our nation has
pursued misguided and unjust policies. Too often we as a nation have
failed to live up to our ideals. We cannot urge other societies to
abide by moral principles without simultaneously admitting our own
society's failure at times to abide by those same principles. We are
united in our conviction - and are confident that all people of good
will in the world will agree - that no appeal to the merits or
demerits of specific foreign policies can ever justify, or even
purport to make sense of, the mass slaughter of innocent persons.
Moreover, in a democracy such as ours, in which government
derives its power from the consent of the governed, policy stems at
least partly from culture, from the values and priorities of the
society as a whole. Though we do not claim to possess full knowledge
of the motivations of our attackers and their sympathizers, what we
do know suggests that their grievances extend far beyond any one
policy, or set of policies. After all, the killers of September 11
issued no particular demands; in this sense, at least, the killing
was done for its own sake. The leader of Al Qaeda described the
"blessed strikes" of September 11 as blows against America, "the
head of world infidelity." Clearly, then, our attackers despise
not just our government, but our overall society, our entire way of
living. Fundamentally, their grievance concerns not only what our
leaders do, but also who we are.
SO WHO ARE WE? What do we value? For many people,
including many Americans and a number of signatories to this letter,
some values sometimes seen in America are unattractive and harmful.
Consumerism as a way of life. The notion of freedom as no rules. The
notion of the individual as self-made and utterly sovereign, owing
little to others or to society. The weakening of marriage and family
life. Plus an enormous entertainment and communications apparatus
that relentlessly glorifies such ideas and beams them, whether they
are welcome or not, into nearly every corner of the globe.
One major task facing us as Americans, important prior to
September 11, is facing honestly these unattractive aspects of our
society and doing all we can to change them for the better. We
pledge ourselves to this effort.
At the same time, other American values - what we view as our
founding ideals, and those that most define our way of life - are
quite different from these, and they are much more attractive, not
only to Americans, but to people everywhere in the world. Let us briefly
mention four of them.
The first is the conviction that all persons possess innate human
dignity as a birthright, and that consequently each person must
always be treated as an end rather than used as a means. The
founders of the United States, drawing upon the natural law
tradition as well as upon the fundamental religious claim that all
persons are created in the image of God, affirmed as "self-evident"
the idea that all persons possess equal dignity. The clearest
political expression of a belief in transcendent human dignity is
democracy. In the United States in recent generations, among the
clearest cultural expressions of this idea has been the affirmation
of the equal dignity of men and women, and of all persons regardless
of race or color.
Second, and following closely from the first, is the conviction
that universal moral truths (what our nation's founders called "laws
of Nature and of Nature's God") exist and are accessible to all
people. Some of the most eloquent expressions of our reliance upon
these truths are found in our Declaration of Independence,
George Washington's Farewell Address, Abraham Lincoln's
Gettysburg Address and Second Inaugural Address, and
Dr. Martin Luther King, Jr.'s Letter from the Birmingham
Jail.
The third is the conviction that, because our individual and
collective access to truth is imperfect, most disagreements about
values call for civility, openness to other views, and reasonable
argument in pursuit of truth.
The fourth is freedom of conscience and freedom of religion.
These intrinsically connected freedoms are widely
recognized, in our own country and elsewhere, as a reflection of
basic human dignity and as a precondition for other individual
freedoms.
To us, what is most striking about these values is that they
apply to all persons without distinction, and cannot be used to
exclude anyone from recognition and respect based on the
particularities of race, language, memory, or religion. That's why
anyone, in principle, can become an American. And in fact, anyone
does. People from everywhere in the world come to our country with
what a statue in New York's harbor calls a yearning to breathe free,
and soon enough, they are Americans. Historically, no other nation
has forged its core identity - its constitution and other founding
documents, as well as its basic self-understanding - so directly and
explicitly on the basis of universal human values. To us, no other
fact about this country is more important.
Some people assert that these values are not universal at all,
but instead derive particularly from western, largely Christian
civilization. They argue that to conceive of these values as
universal is to deny
the distinctiveness of other cultures. We disagree. We recognize
our own civilization's achievements, but we believe that all people
are created equal. We believe in the universal possibility and
desirability of human freedom. We believe that certain basic moral
truths are recognizable everywhere in the world. We agree with the
international group of distinguished philosophers who in the late
1940s helped to shape the United Nations Universal Declaration of
Human Rights, and who concluded that a few fundamental moral ideas
are so widespread that they "may be viewed as implicit
in man's nature as a member of society." In hope, and on the
evidence, we agree with Dr. Martin Luther King, Jr., that the arch
of the moral universe is long, but it bends toward justice, not
just for the few, or the lucky, but for all people.
Looking at our own society, we acknowledge again the all too
frequent gaps between our ideals and our conduct. But as Americans
in a time of war and global crisis, we are also suggesting that the
best of what we too casually call "American values" do not belong
only to America, but are in fact the shared inheritance of
humankind, and therefore a possible basis of hope for a world
community based on peace and justice.
[Back
to Top]
What about God?
SINCE SEPTEMBER 11, millions of Americans have asked
themselves and one another, what about God? Crises of this magnitude
force us to think anew about first principles. When we contemplate
the horror of what has occurred, and the danger of what is likely to
come, many of us ask: Is religious faith part of the solution or
part of the problem?
The signatories to this letter come from diverse religious and
moral traditions, including secular traditions. We are united in our
belief that invoking God's authority to kill or maim human beings is
immoral and is contrary to faith in God. Many of us believe that we
are under God's judgment. None of us believe that God ever instructs
some of us to kill or conquer others of us. Indeed, such an
attitude, whether it is called "holy war" or "crusade," not only
violates basic principles of justice, but is in fact a negation of
religious faith, since it turns God into an
idol to be used for man's own purposes. Our own nation was once
engaged in a great civil war, in which each side presumed God's aid
against the other. In his Second Inaugural Address in 1865,
the sixteenth president of the United States, Abraham Lincoln, put
it simply: "The Almighty has his own purposes."
Those who attacked us on September 11 openly proclaim that they
are engaged in holy war. Many who support or sympathize with the
attackers also invoke God's name and seem to embrace the rationale
of holy war. But to recognize the disaster of this way of thinking,
we as Americans need only to remember our own, and western, history.
Christian religious wars and Christian sectarian violence tore apart
Europe for the better part of a century. In the United States, we
are no strangers to those who would murder at least in part in the
name of their religious faith. When it comes to this particular
evil, no civilization is spotless and no
religious tradition is spotless.
The human person has a basic drive to question in order to know.
Evaluating, choosing, and having reasons for what we value and love
are characteristically
human activities. Part of this intrinsic desire to know concerns
why we are born and what will happen when we die, which leads us to
seek the truth about ultimate ends, including, for many people, the
question of God. Some of the signatories to this letter believe that
human beings are by nature "religious" in the sense that everyone,
including those who do not believe in God and do not participate in
organized religion, makes choices about what is important and
reflects on ultimate values. All of the signatories to this letter
recognize that, across the world, religious faith and religious
institutions are important bases of civil society, often producing
results for society that are beneficial and healing, at times
producing results that are divisive and violent.
So how can governments and societal leaders best respond to these
fundamental human and social realities? One response is to outlaw or
repress religion. Another possible response is to embrace
an ideological secularism: a strong societal skepticism or
hostility regarding religion, based on the premise that religion
itself, and especially any public expression of religious
conviction, is inherently problematic. A third possible response is
to embrace theocracy: the belief that one religion, presumably the
one true religion, should be effectively mandatory for all
members of society and therefore should receive complete or
significant state sponsorship and support.
We disagree with each of these responses. Legal repression
radically violates civil and religious freedom and is incompatible
with democratic civil society. Although ideological secularism may
have increased in our society in recent generations, we disagree
with it because it would deny the public legitimacy of an important
part of civil society as well as seek to suppress or deny the
existence of what is at least arguably an
important dimension of personhood itself. Although theocracy has
been present in western (though not U.S.) history, we disagree with
it for both social and theological reasons. Socially, governmental
establishment of a particular religion can conflict with the
principle of religious freedom, a fundamental human right. In
addition, government control of religion can cause or exacerbate
religious conflicts and, perhaps even more importantly, can threaten
the vitality and authenticity of religious institutions.
Theologically, even for those who are firmly convinced of the truth
of their faith, the coercion of others in matters of religious
conscience is ultimately a violation of religion itself, since it
robs those other persons of the right to respond freely and in
dignity to the Creator's invitation.
At its best, the United States seeks to be a society in which
faith and freedom can go together, each elevating the other. We have
a secular state - our government officials are not simultaneously
religious officials - but we are by far the western world's most
religious society. We are a nation that deeply respects religious
freedom and diversity, including the rights of nonbelievers, but one
whose citizens recite a Pledge of Allegiance to "one nation, under
God," and one that proclaims in many of its courtrooms and inscribes
on each of its coins the motto, "In God We Trust." Politically, our
separation of church and state seeks to keep politics within its
proper sphere, in part by limiting the state's power to control
religion, and in part by causing government itself to draw
legitimacy from, and operate under, a larger moral
canopy that is not of its own making. Spiritually, our
separation of church and state permits religion to be
religion, by detaching it from the coercive power of government. In
short, we seek to separate
church and state for the protection and proper vitality of both.
For Americans of religious faith, the challenge of embracing
religious truth and religious freedom has often been
difficult. The matter, moreover, is never settled. Ours is a social
and constitutional arrangement that almost by definition requires
constant deliberation, debate, adjustment, and compromise. It is
also helped by, and helps to produce, a certain character or
temperament, such that religious believers who strongly embrace the
truth of their faith also, not as a compromise with that truth but
as an aspect of it, respect those who take a different path.
What will help to reduce religiously based mistrust, hatred, and
violence in the 21st century? There are many important answers to
this question, of course, but here, we hope, is one: Deepening and
renewing our appreciation of religion by recognizing religious
freedom as a fundamental right of all people in every nation.
[Back
to Top]
A Just War?
WE RECOGNIZE that all war is terrible, representative
finally of human political failure. We also know that the line
separating good and evil does not run between one society and
another, much less between one religion and another; ultimately,
that line runs through the middle
of every human heart. Finally, those of us - Jews, Christians,
Muslims, and others - who are people of faith recognize our
responsibility, stated in our holy scriptures, to love mercy and to
do all in our power to prevent war and live in peace.
Yet reason and careful moral reflection also teach us that there
are times when the first and most important reply to evil is to stop
it. There are times when waging war is not only morally permitted,
but morally necessary, as a response to calamitous acts of violence,
hatred, and injustice. This is one of those times.
The idea of a "just war" is broadly based, with roots in many of
the world's diverse
religious and secular moral traditions. Jewish, Christian, and
Muslim teachings, for example, all contain serious reflections on
the definition of a just war. To be sure, some people, often in the
name of realism, insist that war is essentially a realm of
self-interest and necessity, making most attempts
at moral analysis irrelevant. We
disagree. Moral inarticulacy in the face of war is itself a
moral stance - one that rejects the possibility of reason, accepts
normlessness in international affairs, and capitulates to cynicism.
To seek to apply objective moral reasoning to war is to defend the
possibility of civil society and a world community based on justice.
The principles of just war teach us that wars of aggression and
aggrandizement are never acceptable. Wars may not legitimately be
fought for national glory, to avenge past wrongs, for territorial
gain, or for any other non-defensive purpose.
The primary moral justification for war is to protect the
innocent from certain harm. Augustine, whose early 5th century book,
The City of God, is a seminal contribution to just war
thinking, argues (echoing
Socrates) that it is better for the Christian as an individual
to suffer harm rather than to commit it. But is the morally
responsible person also required, or even permitted, to make for
other innocent persons a commitment to non-self-defense? For
Augustine, and for the broader just war tradition, the answer is no.
If one has compelling evidence that innocent people who are in no
position to protect themselves will be grievously harmed unless
coercive force is used to stop an aggressor, then the moral
principle of love of neighbor calls us to the use of force.
Wars may not legitimately be fought against dangers that are
small, questionable, or of uncertain consequence, or against dangers
that might
plausibly be mitigated solely through negotiation, appeals to
reason, persuasion from third parties, or other nonviolent
means. But if the danger to innocent life is real and certain,
and especially if the aggressor is motivated by implacable hostility
- if the end he seeks is not your willingness to negotiate or
comply, but rather your destruction - then a resort to proportionate
force is morally justified.
A just war can only be fought by a legitimate authority with
responsibility for public order. Violence
that is free-lance, opportunistic, or individualistic is never
morally acceptable.
A just war can only be waged against persons who are combatants.
Just war authorities from across history and around the world -
whether they be Muslim, Jewish, Christian, from other faith
traditions, or secular - consistently teach us that noncombatants
are immune from deliberate attack. Thus, killing civilians for
revenge, or even as a means of deterring aggression from people who
sympathize with them, is morally wrong. Although in some
circumstances, and within strict limits, it can be morally
justifiable to undertake military actions that may result in the
unintended but foreseeable death or injury of some noncombatants, it
is not morally acceptable to make the killing of noncombatants the
operational objective of a military action.
These and other
just war principles teach us that, whenever human beings
contemplate or wage war, it is both possible and necessary to affirm
the sanctity of human life and embrace the principle of equal human
dignity. These principles strive to preserve and reflect, even in
the tragic activity of war, the fundamental moral truth that
"others" - those who are strangers to us, those who differ from us
in race or language, those whose religions we may believe to be
untrue - have the same right to life that we do, and the same human
dignity and human rights that we do.
ON SEPTEMBER 11, 2001, a group of individuals deliberately
attacked the United States, using highjacked airplanes as weapons
with which to kill in less than two hours over
3,000 of our citizens in New York City, southwestern
Pennsylvania, and Washington, D.C. Overwhelmingly, those who died on
September 11 were civilians, not combatants, and were not known at
all, except as Americans, by those who killed them. Those who died
on the morning of September 11 were killed unlawfully, wantonly, and
with premeditated malice - a kind of killing that, in the name of
precision, can only be described as murder. Those murdered included
people from all races, many ethnicities, most major religions. They
included dishwashers and corporate executives.
The individuals who committed these acts of war did not act
alone, or without support, or for unknown reasons. They were members
of an international Islamicist network, active in as many as 40
countries, now known to the world as Al Qaeda. This group, in turn,
constitutes but one arm of a larger radical Islamicist movement,
growing for decades and in some instances tolerated and even
supported by governments, that openly professes its desire and
increasingly demonstrates its ability to use
murder to advance its objectives.
We use the terms "Islam" and "Islamic" to refer to one of the
world's great religions, with about 1.2 billion adherents, including
several million U.S. citizens, some of whom were murdered on
September 11. It ought to go without saying - but we say it here
once, clearly - that the great majority of the world's Muslims,
guided in large measure by the teachings of the Qur'an, are decent,
faithful, and peaceful. We use the terms "Islamicism" and "radical
Islamicist" to refer to the violent, extremist, and radically
intolerant religious-political movement that now threatens the
world, including the Muslim world.
This radical, violent movement opposes not only certain U.S. and
western policies - some signatories to this letter also oppose some
of those policies - but also a foundational principle of the modern
world, religious tolerance, as well as those fundamental human
rights, in particular freedom of conscience and religion, that are
enshrined in the United Nations Universal Declaration of Human
Rights, and that must be the basis of any civilization oriented to
human flourishing, justice, and peace.
This extremist movement claims to speak for Islam, but betrays
fundamental Islamic principles. Islam sets its face against
moral atrocities. For example, reflecting the teaching of the Qur'an
and the example of the Prophet, Muslim scholars through the
centuries have taught that struggle
in the path of God (i.e., jihad) forbids the deliberate
killing of noncombatants, and requires that military action be
undertaken only at the behest of legitimate public authorities. They
remind
us forcefully that Islam, no less than Christianity, Judaism and
other religions, is threatened and potentially degraded by these
profaners who invoke God's name to kill indiscriminately.
We recognize that movements claiming the mantle of religion also
have complex political, social, and demographic dimensions, to which
due attention must be paid. At the same time, philosophy matters,
and the animating philosophy of this radical Islamicist movement, in
its contempt for human life, and by viewing the world as a
life-and-death struggle between believers and unbelievers (whether
non-radical Muslims, Jews, Christians, Hindus, or others), clearly
denies the equal dignity of all persons and, in doing so, betrays
religion and rejects the very foundation of civilized life and the
possibility of peace among nations.
Most seriously of all, the mass murders of September 11
demonstrated, arguably for the first time, that this movement now
possesses not only the openly stated desire, but also the capacity
and expertise - including possible access to, and willingness to
use, chemical, biological and nuclear weapons - to wreak massive,
horrific devastation
on its intended targets.
Those who slaughtered more than 3,000 persons on September 11 and
who, by their own admission, want nothing more than to do it again,
constitute a clear and present danger to all people of good will
everywhere in the world, not just the United States. Such acts are a
pure example of naked aggression against innocent human life, a
world-threatening evil that clearly requires the use of force to
remove it.
Organized killers with global reach now threaten all of us. In
the name of universal human morality, and fully conscious of the
restrictions and requirements of a just war, we support our
government's, and our society's, decision to use force of arms
against them.
[Back
to Top]
Conclusion
WE PLEDGE TO DO all we can to guard against the harmful
temptations - especially those of arrogance and jingoism - to which
nations at war so often seem to yield. At the same time, with one
voice we say solemnly that it is crucial for our nation and its
allies to win this war. We fight to defend ourselves, but we also
believe that we fight to defend those universal principles of human
rights and human dignity that are the best hope for humankind.
One day, this war will end. When it does - and in some respects
even before it ends - the great task of conciliation awaits us. We
hope that this war, by stopping an unmitigated global evil, can
increase the possibility of a world community based on justice. But
we know that only the peacemakers among us in every society can
ensure that this war will not have been in vain.
We wish especially to reach out to our brothers and sisters in
Muslim societies. We say to you forthrightly: We are not enemies, but
friends. We must not be enemies. We have so much in common.
There is so much that we must do together. Your human dignity, no
less than ours - your rights and opportunities for a good life, no
less than ours - are what we believe we're fighting for. We know
that, for some of you, mistrust of us is high, and we know that we
Americans are partly responsible for that mistrust. But we must not
be enemies. In hope, we wish to join with you and all people of good
will to build a just and lasting peace.
[Back
to Top]
Signatories
Enola Aird Director, The Motherhood Project; Council on
Civil Society
John Atlas President, National Housing Institute; Executive
Director, Passaic County Legal Aid Society
Jay Belsky Professor and Director, Institute for the Study
of Children, Families and Social Issues, Birkbeck University of
London
David Blankenhorn President, Institute for American
Values
David Bosworth University of Washington
R. Maurice Boyd Minister, The City Church, New York
Gerard V. Bradley Professor of Law, University of Notre
Dame
Margaret F. Brinig Edward A. Howry Distinguished Professor,
University of Iowa College of Law
Allan Carlson President, The Howard Center for Family,
Religion, and Society
Khalid Durán Editor, TransIslam Magazine
Paul Ekman Professor of Psychology, University of
California, San Francisco
Jean Bethke Elshtain Laura Spelman Rockefeller Professor of
Social and Political Ethics, University of Chicago Divinity
School
Amitai Etzioni University Professor, The George Washington
University
Hillel Fradkin President, Ethics and Public Policy
Center
Samuel G. Freedman Professor at the Columbia University
Graduate School of Journalism
Francis Fukuyama Bernard Schwartz Professor of
International Political Economy, Johns Hopkins University
William A. Galston Professor at the School of Public
Affairs, University of Maryland; Director, Institute for Philosophy
and Public Policy
Claire Gaudiani Senior research scholar, Yale Law School
and former president, Connecticut College
Robert P. George McCormick Professor of Jurisprudence and
Professor of Politics, Princeton University
Neil Gilbert Professor at the School of Social Welfare,
University of California, Berkeley
Mary Ann Glendon Learned Hand Professor of Law, Harvard
University Law School
Norval D. Glenn Ashbel Smith Professor of Sociology and
Stiles Professor of American Studies, University of Texas at
Austin
Os Guinness Senior Fellow, Trinity Forum
David Gutmann Professor Emeritus of Psychiatry and
Education, Northwestern University
Kevin J. "Seamus" Hasson President, Becket Fund for
Religious Liberty
Sylvia Ann Hewlett Chair, National Parenting
Association
James Davison Hunter William R. Kenan, Jr., Professor of
Sociology and Religious Studies and Executive Director, Center on
Religion and Democracy, University of Virginia
Samuel Huntington Albert J. Weatherhead, III, University
Professor, Harvard University
Byron Johnson Director and Distinguished Senior Fellow,
Center for Research on Religion and Urban Civil Society, University
of Pennsylvania
James Turner Johnson Professor, Department of Religion,
Rutgers University
John Kelsay Richard L. Rubenstein Professor of Religion,
Florida State University
Diane Knippers President, Institute on Religion and
Democracy
Thomas C. Kohler Professor of Law, Boston College Law
School
Glenn C. Loury Professor of Economics and Director,
Institute on Race and Social Division, Boston University
Harvey C. Mansfield William R. Kenan, Jr., Professor of
Government, Harvard University
Will Marshall President, Progressive Policy Institute
Richard J. Mouw President, Fuller Theological
Seminary
Daniel Patrick Moynihan University Professor, Maxwell
School of Citizenship and Public Affairs, Syracuse
University
John E. Murray, Jr. Chancellor and Professor of Law,
Duquesne University
Michael Novak George Frederick Jewett Chair in Religion and
Public Policy, American Enterprise Institute
Rev. Val J. Peter Executive Director, Boys and Girls
Town
David Popenoe Professor of Sociology and Co-Director of the
National Marriage Project, Rutgers University
Robert D. Putnam Peter and Isabel Malkin Professor of
Public Policy at the Kennedy School of Government, Harvard
University
Gloria G. Rodriguez Founder and President, AVANCE,
Inc.
Robert Royal President, Faith & Reason
Institute
Nina Shea Director, Freedom's House's Center for Religious
Freedom
Fred Siegel Professor of History, The Cooper Union
Theda Skocpol Victor S. Thomas Professor of Government and
Sociology, Harvard University
Katherine Shaw Spaht Jules and Frances Landry Professor of
Law, Louisiana State University Law Center
Max L. Stackhouse Professor of Christian Ethics and
Director, Project on Public Theology, Princeton Theological
Seminary
William Tell, Jr. The William and Karen Tell
Foundation
Maris A. Vinovskis Bentley Professor of History and
Professor of Public Policy, University of Michigan
Paul C. Vitz Professor of Psychology, New York
University
Michael Walzer Professor at the School of Social Science,
Institute for Advanced Study
George Weigel Senior Fellow, Ethics and Public Policy
Center
Charles Wilson Director, Center for the Study of Southern
Culture, University of Mississippi
James Q. Wilson Collins Professor of Management and Public
Policy Emeritus, UCLA
John Witte, Jr. Jonas Robitscher Professor of Law and
Ethics and Director, Law and Religion Program, Emory University Law
School
Christopher Wolfe Professor of Political Science, Marquette
University
Daniel Yankelovich President, Public Agenda
[Back
to Top]
Endnotes
Preamble
human beings are born free:
From the United Nations Universal Declaration of Human Rights,
Article 1.
basic subject of society: A
Call to Civil Society (New York: Institute for American Values,
1998), 16; Aristotle, Politics VII, 1-2.
Human beings naturally
desire to seek the truth: Aristotle, Metaphysics, 1-1;
John Paul II, Fides et Ratio, 25 (Vatican City, 1998).
Religious freedom: United
Nations Universal Declaration of Human Rights, Articles 18-19.
Killing in the name
of God: Bosphorus Declaration (Istanbul, Turkey, February 9,
1994); Berne Declaration (Wolfsberg/Zurich, Switzerland, November
26, 1992); and John Paul II, Papal Message for World Day of Peace,
Articles 6-7 (Vatican City, January 1, 2002).
What are American
Values?
"the head of
world infidelity": "Excerpt: Bin Laden Tape," Washington
Post, December 27, 2001.
briefly mention four of
them: See A Call to Civil Society (New York: Institute
for American Values, 1998).
widely recognized...as a
precondition for other individual freedoms: See John Witte Jr.
and M. Christian Green, "The American Constitutional Experiment in
Religious Human Rights: The Perennial Search for Principles," in
Johan D. van der Vyver and John Witte, Jr. (eds.), Religious
Human Rights in Global Perspective, vol. 2 (The Hague: Martinus
Nijhoff Publishers, 1996). See also Harold J. Berman, Law and
Revolution: The Formation of the Western Legal Tradition
(Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1983); and Michael J.
Perry, The Idea of Human Rights: Four Inquiries (New York:
Oxford University Press, 1998).
deny the
distinctiveness of other cultures: Some people make this point
as a way of condemning those "other" cultures that are presumably
too inferior, or too enthralled by false beliefs, to appreciate what
we in this letter are calling universal human values; others make
this point as a way of endorsing (usually one of) those
cultures that are presumably indifferent to these values. We
disagree with both versions of this point.
implicit in man's
nature as a member of society: Richard McKeon, "The Philosophic
Bases and Material Circumstances of the Rights of Man," in Human
Rights: Comments and Interpretations (London: Wingate, 1949),
45.
arch of the moral
universe is long, but it bends toward justice: Martin Luther
King, Jr., "Where Do We Go From Here?", in James M. Washington
(ed.), The Essential Writings and Speeches of Martin Luther King,
Jr. (New York: HarperCollins, 1986), 245.
What about God?
an idol to be used for man's
own purposes: John Paul II, Papal Message for World Day of
Peace, Article 6 (Vatican City, January 1, 2002).
no religious tradition is
spotless: Intra-Christian examples of holy war or crusade
emerged with particular force in Europe during the 17th century.
According to some scholars, the principle characteristics of holy
war are: that the cause for which the war is fought has a clear
connection to religion (i.e., that the cause is "holy"); that the
war is fought under the banner and with the presumption of divine
authority and assistance (the Latin term used by 11th century
Christian crusaders was "Deus Volt," or "God wills it"); that
the warriors understand themselves to be godly, or "warrior saints";
that the war is prosecuted zealously and unsparingly, since the
enemy is presumed to be ungodly and therefore fundamentally "other,"
lacking the human dignity and rights of the godly; and finally, that
warriors who die in battle are favored by God as martyrs.
Eventually, in Christianity, the development of just war doctrine,
with its emphasis on moral universalism, largely called for the
elimination of religion as a just cause for war. As early as the
16th century, some natural law theorists such as Franciscus de
Victoria and Francisco Suarez were explicitly condemning the use of
war to spread religion. "Difference in religion," Victoria wrote,
"is not a cause of just war." See James Turner Johnson, Ideology,
Reason, and the Limitation of War: Religious and Secular Concepts
1200 - 1740 (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1975),
112-123, 154. See also Roland H. Bainton, Christian Attitudes
Toward War and Peace: A Historical Survey and Critical
Re-evaluation (Nashville: Abingdon, 1960), 148.
characteristically
human activities: A Call to Civil Society (New York:
Institute for American Values, 1998): 16. This theme is developed in
Aristotle, Metaphysics, 1-1; Bernard J. Lonergan, Insight:
A Study of Human Understanding (New York: Longmans, 1958); and
others.
embrace an ideological
secularism: We wish here to distinguish "secular" from
"secularism." Secular, derived from the Latin term meaning "world"
and suggesting "in the world," refers merely to functions that are
separate from the church. Secularism, by contrast, is a philosophy,
an "ism," a way of seeing the world based on rejection of religion
or hostility to religion.
an important dimension of
personhood itself: For this reason, advocates of secularism may
underestimate the degree to which human societies, even in theory,
can simply dispense with "religion." Moreover, they almost certainly
miscalculate, even accepting many of their own premises, the social
consequences of suppressing traditional religion. For if we
understand religion to be values of ultimate concern, the 20th
century saw two world-threatening examples - Nazism in Germany, and
communism in the Soviet Union - of the emergence of secular
religions, or what might be called replacement religions, each
violently intent on eliminating its society's traditional religious
faiths (in effect, its competitor faiths), and each, when in power,
ruthlessly indifferent to human dignity and basic human rights.
separate church and
state for the protection and proper vitality of both: As the
leaders and scholars who produced The Williamsburg Charter
put it in 1988, "the government acts as a safeguard, but not the
source, of freedom for faiths, whereas the churches and synagogues
act as a source, but not the safeguard, of faiths for freedom . . .
The result is neither a naked public square where all religion is
excluded, nor a sacred public square with any religion established
or semi-established. The result, rather, is a civil public square in
which citizens of all religious faiths, or none, engage one another
in the continuing democratic discourse." See James Davison Hunter
and Os Guinness (eds.), Articles of Faith, Articles of Peace: The
Religious Liberty Clauses and the American Public Philosophy
(Washington, D.C.: The Brookings Institution, 1990), 140.
moral canopy that is not of its own
making: A Call to Civil Society (New York: Institute for
American Values, 1998): 13.
A Just War?
middle of every human
heart: see Alexander Solzhenitzyn, The Gulag
Archipelago, vol. I (New York: Harper and Row, 1974), 168.
diverse religious
and secular moral traditions: See Jean Bethke Elshtain (ed.),
Just War Theory (Oxford: Blackwell, 1992); Elshtain, Stanley
Hauerwas, and James Turner Johnson, Pew Forum on Religion and Public
Life Conference on "Just War Tradition and the New War on Terrorism"
(http://pewforum.org/events/1005/);
James Turner Johnson, Ideology, Reason, and the Limitation of
War: Religious and Secular Concepts 1200 - 1740 (Princeton:
Princeton University Press, 1975); Johnson, Just War Tradition
and the Restraint of War: A Moral and Historical Inquiry
(Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1981); Johnson, The Quest
for Peace: Three Moral Traditions in Western Cultural History
(Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1987); Johnson, Morality
and Contemporary Warfare (New Haven: Yale University Press,
1999); Johnson and John Kelsay (eds.), Cross, Crescent, and
Sword: The Justification and Limitation of War in Western and
Islamic Tradition (New York: Greenwood Press, 1990); Majid
Khadduri, War and Peace in the Law of Islam (Baltimore: Johns
Hopkins University Press, 1955); John Kelsay and James Turner
Johnson (eds.), Just War and Jihad: Historical and Theoretical
Perspectives on War and Peace in Western and Islamic Tradition
(New York: Greenwood Press, 1991); Terry Nardin (ed.), The Ethics
of War and Peace: Religious and Secular Perspectives (Princeton:
Princeton University Press, 1996); William V. O'Brien, The
Conduct of War and Limited War (New York: Praeger, 1981); Rudolf
Peters, Jihad in Classical and Modern Islam (Princeton:
Markus Wiener, 1996); Paul Ramsey, Speak Up for Just War or
Pacifism (University Park, PA: Pennsylvania State University
Press, 1988); Michael Walzer, Just and Unjust Wars (New York:
Basic Books, 1977); and Richard Wasserstrom (ed.), War and
Morality (Belmont, CA: Wadsworth, 1970).
attempts at moral
analysis irrelevant: The Latin axiom is: Inter arma silent
leges (In times of war the law is silent). Classical exemplars
of this perspective include Thucydides, Niccolo Machiavelli and
Thomas Hobbes; for a more recent treatment, see Kenneth Waltz,
Man, the State and War (Princeton: Princeton University
Press, 1978). For a sensitive but critical survey of the
contribution of this school of thought to international theory, see
Jack Donnelly, Realism and International Relations
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000).
We disagree: Intellectual and
moral approaches to war as a human phenomenon can generally be
divided into four schools of thought. The first can be called
realism: the belief that war is basically a matter of power,
self-interest, necessity, and survival, thereby rendering abstract
moral analysis largely beside the point. The second can be called
holy war: the belief that God can authorize the coercion and killing
of nonbelievers, or that a particular secular ideology of ultimate
concern can authorize the coercion and killing of nonbelievers. The
third can be called pacifism: the belief that all war is
intrinsically immoral. And the fourth is typically called just war:
the belief that universal moral reasoning, or what some would call
natural moral law, can and should be applied to the activity of war.
The signatories to this letter largely disagree with the first
school of thought. We unequivocally reject the second school of
thought, regardless of the form it takes, or whether it springs from
and purports to support our own society ("our side") or the side of
those who wish us ill. Some of the signatories have much respect for
the third school of thought (particularly its insistence that
non-violence does not mean retreat or passivity or declining to
stand for justice; quite the opposite), even as we respectfully, and
with some degree of fear and trembling, differ from it. As a group
we seek largely to embrace and build upon the fourth school of
thought.
(echoing Socrates):
Socrates' judgment that it is better to suffer evil rather than to
do it is conveyed to us by Plato in the Apology (32-c to
32-e) and constitutes a key moment in moral philosophy.
might plausibly be
mitigated solely through...non-violent means: Some people
suggest that the "last resort" requirement of just war theory - in
essence, the requirement to explore all other reasonable and
plausible alternatives to the use of force - is not satisfied until
the resort to arms has been approved by a recognized international
body, such as the United Nations. This proposition is problematic.
First, it is novel; historically, approval by an international body
has not been viewed by just war theorists as a just cause
requirement. Second, it is quite debatable whether an international
body such as the U.N. is in a position to be the best final judge of
when, and under what conditions, a particular resort to arms is
justified; or whether the attempt by that body to make and enforce
such judgments would inevitably compromise its primary mission of
humanitarian work. According to one observer, a former U.N.
Assistant Secretary-General, transforming the U.N. into "a pale
imitation of a state" in order to "manage the use of force"
internationally "may well be a suicidal embrace." See Giandomenico
Picco, "The U.N. and the Use of Force," Foreign Affairs 73
(1994): 15. See also Thomas G. Weis, David P. Forsythe, and Roger A.
Coate, United Nations and Changing World Politics (Boulder,
CO: Westview Press, 2001), 104-106; and John Gerard Ruggie, The
United Nations and the Collective Use of Force: Whither? Or
Whether? (New York: United Nations Association of the USA,
1996).
Violence that is
free-lance...is never morally acceptable: In just war theory,
the main goal of the legitimate authority requirement is to prevent
the anarchy of private warfare and warlords - an anarchy that exists
today in some parts of the world, and of which the attackers of
September 11 are representative embodiments. The legitimate
authority requirement does not, on the other hand, for several
reasons, apply clearly or directly to wars of national independence
or succession. First, these latter types of conflict occur within a
state, not internationally. Moreover, in many such conflicts, the
question of public legitimacy is exactly what is being contested.
For example, in the war for independence that resulted in the
founding of the United States, just war analysts frequently point
out that the rebelling colonies themselves constituted a legitimate
public authority, and further that the colonies had reasonably
concluded that the British government had, in the words of our
Declaration of Independence, become "destructive of these ends" of
legitimate government, and therefore itself had ceased to function
as a competent public authority. Indeed, even in cases in which
those waging war do not in any plain sense constitute a currently
functioning public authority - for example, the "Warsaw Ghetto
Uprising" of Polish Jews in 1943 against the Nazi occupation - the
legitimate authority requirement of just war theory does not morally
invalidate the resort to arms by those resisting oppression by
seeking to overthrow illegitimate authority.
other just war
principles: For example, just war principles often insist that
legitimate warfare must be motivated by the intention of enhancing
the likelihood of peace and reducing the likelihood of violence and
destruction; that it must be proportionate, such that the social
goods that would result from victory in war discernably outweigh the
evils that will attend the war; that it must contain the probability
of success, such that lives are not taken and sacrificed in futile
causes; and that it must pass the test of comparative justice, such
that the human goods being defended are important enough, and
gravely enough in danger, to outweigh what many just war theorists
view as the standing moral presumption against war. This letter
focuses largely on principles of justice in declaring war (in the
terminology employed by many Christian just war thinkers, jus ad
bellum) and in waging war (jus in bello). Other
principles focus on justice in settling the war and restoring
conditions of peace (jus post bellum). See Jean Bethke
Elshtain (ed.), Just War Theory (Oxford: Blackwell, 1992);
U.S. Conference of Catholic Bishops, The Challenge of Peace:
God's Promise and Our Response (Washington, D.C.: United States
Catholic Conference, 1983); and other sources cited above.
over 3,000 of our
citizens: As of January 4, 2002, official estimates were that
3,119 persons had been killed by the September 11 attackers,
including 2,895 in New York, 184 in Washington, and 40 in
Pennsylvania. Although this letter refers to "our citizens,"
included among those murdered on September 11 were many citizens of
other countries who were living in the U.S. at the time of the
attack. "Dead and Missing," New York Times, January 8, 2002.
use murder to advance its
objectives: In addition to the murders of September 11, members
of radical Islamicist organizations are apparently responsible for:
the April 18, 1983 bombing of the U.S. Embassy in Beirut, killing 63
persons and injuring 120; the October 23, 1983 bombings of U.S.
Marine and French paratroop barracks in Beirut, killing 300 persons;
the December 21, 1988 bombing of U.S. Pan Am Flight 103, killing 259
persons; the February 26, 1993 bombing of the World Trade Center in
New York City, killing six persons and injuring 1000; the June 25,
1996 bombing outside the Khobar Towers U.S. military barracks in
Dhahran, Saudi Arabia, killing 19 U.S. soldiers and wounding 515;
the August 7, 1998 bombing of U.S. embassies in Nairobi, Kenya, and
Dar es Salaam, Tanzania, killing 224 persons and injuring more than
5,000; and the October 12, 2000 bombing of the USS Cole in Aden,
Yemen, killing 17 U.S. sailors and wounding 39. This list is
incomplete. (See Significant Terrorist Incidents, 1961-2001
(Washington, D.C.: U.S. Department of State, Bureau of Public
Affairs, October 31, 2001). In addition, members of organizations
comprising this movement are also responsible for numerous failed
attempts at mass murder, both in the U.S. and in other countries,
including the attempt to bomb the United Nations and the Lincoln and
Holland Tunnels in New York in 1993 and the attempt to bomb the Los
Angeles International Airport on New Year's Eve 2000.
struggle in the path of God
(i.e., jihad) forbids: The relationship between the
jihad and just war traditions is complex. Premodern
jihad and just war perspectives overlapped in important ways.
Both could legitimate wars aimed at advancing religion, and both
sought clearly to disassociate such wars from wars involving
indiscriminate or disproportionate tactics. In the modern era,
jihad has largely retained its confessional component - that
is, its aim of protecting and propagating Islam as a religion. The
confessional dimension of jihad thinking in turn seems to be
closely linked to the view of the state widely held by Muslim
authorities - a view that envisions little or no separation of
religion from the state. By contrast, modern Christian thinking on
just war has tended to downplay its confessional elements (few
Christian theologians today emphasize the value of "crusade"),
replacing them with more religiously neutral arguments about human
rights and shared moral norms, or what some Christian and other
thinkers term "natural moral law." Some Muslim scholars today seek,
in the case of jihad, more fully to recover the sense of the
term as "exertion" or "striving for good" in the service of God,
thereby similarly downplaying its confessional elements and
emphasizing, for our increasingly plural and interdependent world,
the term's more universal dimensions and applications. For example,
see Sohail M. Hashmi, "Interpreting the Islamic Ethics of War and
Peace," in Terry Nardin (ed.), The Ethics of War and Peace:
Religious and Secular Perspectives (Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press, 1996), 146-166; and Hilmi Zawati, Is Jihad a
Just War? War, Peace, and Human Rights under Islamic and Public
International Law (Lewiston, NY: Edwin Mellen, 2001).
Muslim scholars...remind us
forcefully: For example, Muslim scholars affiliated with the
Muslim World League, meeting in Mecca, recently reaffirmed that
jihad strictly prohibits "the killing of noncombatants" and attacks
against "installations, sites and buildings not related to the
fighting." See "Muslim scholars define 'terrorism' as opposed to
legitimate jihad," Middle East News Online [http://www.middleeastwire.com/],
posted January 14, 2002. See also Bassam Tibi, "War and Peace in
Islam," in Terry Nardin (ed.), The Ethics of War and Peace:
Religious and Secular Perspectives (Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press, 1996), 128-145.
devastation
on its intended targets: The historian Eric Hobsbawm, in his
study of the 20th century, published in 1995, warns us in
particular, as we confront the new millennium, of the emerging
crisis of "non-state terrorism," made possible by the growing
"privatization of the means of destruction," such that organized
groups, operating at least to some degree independently of public
authorities, are increasingly willing and able to perpetrate
"violence and wreckage anywhere on the globe." Eric Hobsbawm, Age
of Extremes: The Short Twentieth Century 1914-1991 (London:
Abacus, 1995), 560.
Conclusion
but friends: From Abraham Lincoln,
First Inaugural Address, March 1861.
[Back
to Top]
(c) February 2002, Institute for American Values
ISBN:1-931764-02-6
For information or additional copies, contact:
Institute for American Values 1841 Broadway, Suite 211 New
York, NY 10023 Tel: (212) 246-3942 Fax: (212) 541-6665
Email: info@americanvalues.org
Website: http://www.americanvalues.org/
The signatories wish to thank Dan Cere of McGill University in
Montreal for research and editorial assistance.
[Back
to Top]
|