IN
THE WAKE of September 11, what can a psychiatrist contribute
to America's defense? Nothing, of course, to defend the nation
from bombs, but something perhaps to defend it against
confusion--and here America certainly needs help.
At
the University of Pennsylvania, the provost called several
neuroscientists together to consider whether the terrorists
should be viewed as bad or mad: evildoers or sufferers from an
exculpating mental disease. The group reached no conclusion,
but one participant thought "brain images" might give the
answer.
Editorialists argued about whether the
atrocities should be considered acts of war or crimes. The
blame-America-first group wanted the events called crimes and
proposed prosecutions at the Hague. Some even opposed military
retaliation, concerned that it would kill innocent people,
produce martyrs, and generate recruits to the terrorist cause,
along with endless war.
One distinguished Boston
psychiatrist, speaking to anchorman Peter Jennings on ABC,
explained the emotional distress of Americans as castration
anxiety provoked by seeing the destruction of these two
"phallic symbols" on the tip of Manhattan and suggested more
psychoanalytic insight for us all.
Against this
backdrop, there may be a place for some psychological
realism--about what terrorists do, how they think, the steps
necessary to protect ourselves from them, and the price those
steps are likely to exact from us. The observations that
follow spring from long clinical experience with similar
matters. The layman should judge them by the light of common
sense and what he knows about the ways of the world. Where
these insights overlap with and reinforce ideas from other
relevant sources--diplomatic, legal, economic, military--they
may enhance confidence in the course of action we must take.
A REALISt can begin by rejecting the
castration-anxiety idea--even though it provided the only
humor in the whole affair. Americans felt emotional distress
not because the towers of the World Trade Center were longer
than they were wide, but because witnessing the cruel deaths
of so many of our fellow citizens--horribly killed as they
went about their daily lives, unsuspecting and
unprotected--naturally provokes grief, anger, and fear. The
brutal, indiscriminate slaughter of thousands of people in an
instant, along with the sight of their bodies dropping like
debris from dizzying heights, should produce pity, grief, rage
in anyone with an ounce of fellow-feeling.
Next,
having rejected a far-fetched theory, the pragmatic behavioral
scientist sets aside for the time being questions about
whether the actions at issue were mad or bad, crimes or acts
of war, and examines the phenomenon of terrorism itself. The
hijacking of airplanes and the piloting of them as missiles
into large buildings, he notes, the deliberate targeting of
civilians with the aim of producing fear, dread, and their
political profits, is purposeful action. It is behavior.
Terrorist behavior is different from behavior such as
eating, drinking, or sex in that it springs not from any
innate drive or instinctive motive, but from a set of
assumptions, attitudes, and beliefs that the actors have taken
from their culture and share with many others. In contrast to
their fellow citizens, however, these actors bring a ferocious
passion to these ideas, a passion that leads them to ignore
all other considerations such as personal safety, humane
feelings, compromise, or temporizing alternatives.
In
everyday speech, we call such people "fanatics."
Psychiatrists, however, have their own, less loaded term. They
say that people with this passionate attitude have an
"overvalued idea." This conceptual distinction in mental life
was first made by the late-19th-century German psychiatrist
Carl Wernicke.
An overvalued idea is a thought shared
with others in a society or culture but in the patient held
with an intense emotional commitment capable of provoking
dominant behaviors in its service. An overvalued idea differs
from a delusion in that delusions are false ideas unique to
the possessor, whereas overvalued ideas develop from
assumptions and beliefs shared by many others. An overvalued
idea differs, too, from an obsession in that, although it
dominates the mind as an obsession does, the subject does not
fight an overvalued idea but instead relishes, amplifies, and
defends it. Indeed the idea fulminates in the mind of the
subject, growing more dominant over time, more refined, and
more resistant to challenge.
The major contemporary
clinical disorder prompted by an overvalued idea is anorexia
nervosa. Patients suffering from this illness take an idea
common among young women in our society--thinner is
better--and amplify it into a commitment so dominant that they
starve themselves. At first an anorexic may claim that she is
no different from any woman "thinking thin." As she persists
with a worrisome starvation diet, she may justify eating only
low fat salads as her way to "health." All therapeutic
attempts to correct the behavior by dissuading her of this
idea or uncovering its root cause fail, because the overvalued
idea--one cannot be too thin--resists logical argument and
compromise. Only stopping the behavior--which may require
bringing the patient under 24 hour supervision--can lead the
anorexic to recover.
But overvalued ideas also crop up
outside the clinical setting. Two recent examples of
individuals with overvalued ideas are the Unabomber and Jack
Kevorkian. The Unabomber, preoccupied with what he saw as the
materialism and destructive reliance on technology of our
society, carried out vicious and cowardly letter bomb assaults
against many defenseless people he associated with these
enterprises. When his rambling, expansive, and tedious
explanations were published in the Washington Post, many
readers reported that they agreed with much of what he said.
Jack Kevorkian, despite killing scores of sick,
emotionally vulnerable people in Michigan, persuaded several
juries that his ideas about assisted suicide were well
intended, even though contrary to law. Juries repeatedly freed
him, until his indiscriminate killing and disdain for the
courts became too much to stomach. Kevorkian and the Unabomber
now sit in jail because only incarceration could keep them
from continuing their violence. Neither of them is mad in the
sense of being out of contact with reality, but both of them
are bad because of their vile opinions and vicious behavior.
Their "brain images" would make no difference to such
judgments.
Three historical figures with overvalued
ideas are Adolf Hitler with his anti-Semitism, Carrie Nation
with her excessive devotion to temperance, and John Brown the
abolitionist. Note that an overvalued idea may not in itself
be wrong. Enough people agreed with Carrie Nation to pass the
18th Amendment; and all now agree with John Brown that slavery
is evil, even though they deplore his assaults on defenseless
farmers in Kansas and his killing spree at Harpers Ferry.
Overvalued ideas develop as ruling passions in some
vulnerable individuals. Anorexics tend to be introverted young
women, impressionable and easily conditioned by criticism of
their physical appearance. The Unabomber, Jack Kevorkian, and
the World Trade Center terrorists also tended to a personality
type, arrogant and over-confident, suspicious of others,
lacking in warmth, and tediously argumentative, shifting their
ground to justify their fixed opinions when faced with strong
objections. Cold, paranoid, and aggressive are terms that
describe them. All efforts to correct the behavior of such
people by addressing its "root causes" will fail because those
"causes" are not actually motivating these people's
behavior--their passions are.
DEFINING the
September 11 attacks as behavior and the terrorists as men
driven by the overvalued idea that America is a satanic nation
whose citizens deserve death has implications for ways of
defeating them. Here, recent psychiatric experience in
treating behavior disorders can help.
Before about
1975, psychiatrists treating patients with destructive
behaviors such as anorexia, alcoholism, and sexual disorders
believed that one should first find the psychological roots of
these behaviors by uncovering their meaning in the patient's
mental conflicts. They thought that if these meaningful
conflicts could be resolved, the abnormal behavior would
wither away. This approach failed. Treatment programs for
anorexia, for example, that ignored the failure to eat while
attending to its meaning had death rates of between 10 percent
and 15 percent of their patients. Alcoholics continued to
drink, sex offenders to offend, even while their psychiatrists
claimed to be reaching an understanding of their problems.
These results eventually caused doctors to try
treatments that directly interrupted the harmful behavior.
Anorexics were brought under dietary supervision, alcoholics
were detoxified and sent to clinics implementing the 12 step
program of Alcoholics Anonymous, and sex offenders were given
testosterone-suppressing medications and vigorous group
therapy concentrated on discrediting their activities and
their justifications. These treatments worked far better: Many
more anorexics, alcoholics, and sex offenders recovered.
This experience taught psychiatrists that behavior,
once begun, maintains itself. Anorexics like to see their
weight and dress size steadily shrink. Alcoholics, drug
addicts, and sex offenders get immediate pleasurable
reinforcement to continue their activities.
The same
is true of terrorists: Their behavior is maintained by its
consequences, especially the publicity that draws attention to
the terrorist and his ideas. The Unabomber hated to be pushed
off center stage by Timothy McVeigh and so killed two more
people right after the Oklahoma City bombing. Jack Kevorkian
started videotaping his killings for CBS TV when Michigan
ceased bringing him to court. Although the September 11
terrorists died in their assault, they were sure of worldwide
publicity for their actions and their views. Their success
brought dancing to the streets in certain Muslim cities and
recruits to their war against America--far more recruits than
any "root cause" of terrorism, such as poverty or anger at
Israel, had brought.
By implication, then, to stop
terrorism, the American government should devote its energies
to interrupting the terrorists' behavior in all its aspects.
The government should use every reasonable method to apprehend
individuals who could carry out terrorist actions. It should
protect vulnerable sites and situations. And most crucially,
it should alter the consequences of the September 11 assault:
To our injuries it should promptly add injuries to those
responsible for the attack.
This policy should be
judged simply and tough-mindedly by its success in preventing
more terrorist behavior. Preventing terrorist events must be
our prime aim, not just because each atrocity is an evil in
itself, but also because terrorism, like every other behavior,
grows with its performance. To accommodate ourselves to it as
a "fact of life" is to sustain it.
Our government can
ignore certain matters for the moment. We should not expend
much energy unearthing the "preconditions" for terrorism or
pay credence to the justifying explanations offered by
spokesmen for terrorists, no matter how reasonable they may
seem. In truth, there are as many reasons offered for
terrorism as there are terrorists--just as Alcoholics
Anonymous has learned that there are as many reasons offered
for drinking as there are drunks.
Stop the behavior
first, and then, once peace is restored, we can deal with
underlying issues. We will very likely find that many of the
justifications now offered for terrorism were only
rationalizations intended to excuse it. But we need not waste
our energies trying to change the opinions of terrorists about
us and our aims. These people, like the Unabomber and Jack
Kevorkian, have overvalued ideas that are inaccessible to
argument and persuasion. Their behavior will continue unless
they are captured or killed.
Whether we call the
terrorists' atrocities acts of war or crimes should be
determined by one thing: which term best helps us stop the
behavior. It seems more likely that we can keep terrorists
from striking again if we treat them as soldiers captured
committing acts of war on a battlefield of their own devising
than if we treat them as individuals indicted for crimes and
innocent until proven guilty. The IRA terrorists and
sympathizers confined to the Maze prison at Long Kesh in
Northern Ireland demanded the status of soldier-prisoners
rather than criminal-prisoners. Certainly our laws can
accommodate their Muslim counterparts.
FINALLY, what of the concern that military
action will generate martyrs, draw recruits to the terrorists'
cause, and produce endless conflict? Psychiatrists are
familiar with this worry. It crops up whenever they propose a
treatment aimed at interrupting a behavior. Patients and
relatives all see and object to the intrusion on the patient's
autonomy--such as the demand that the anorexic stay in a
hospital so that her eating can be supervised or the
requirement that the sex offender take libido-reducing
medications. They wonder whether this will only cause patients
to "dig in their heels" or "lose self-esteem." They propose
that the psychiatrist should discover and resolve some
meaningful conflict behind the behavior and so spare the
patient a distressing treatment. Psychiatrists must explain to
patients and their families that every effort to interrupt or
change behavior elicits short-term losses, which are the price
of recovery. Clinicians must weigh the inevitable short-term
losses against the potential long-term gains.
Sometimes the likely losses are excessive. The classic
illustration is stopping a lynch mob. One had best not attempt
this alone, as the short-term cost to oneself could be
terminal. Better to bring an army to stop a mob. Then, after
order is restored and the hard feelings that are the
short-term cost of preventing the crowd from working its will
have dissipated, work to end the ideas and attitudes that
support lynching.
In America's effort to interrupt the
behavior of terrorists, many of whom are nestled in our
country, the government may need laws that temporarily reduce
civil liberties. We may have to go on a war footing, with
special authority turned over temporarily to the military. We
may have to sacrifice privileges in travel and tax relief.
Discussion and careful judgments should aim to minimize and
justify these losses. All such measures should be reassessed
regularly. But they should be understood as the inevitable
short-term costs of interrupting terrorist behavior.
The same sort of reasoning applies to our dealings
with other countries. We have spent decades building up
certain political and diplomatic relationships during
peacetime. Some of these relationships will be damaged as we
vigorously bring war to terrorists and their sympathizers and
demand help from those who would call us friends. Again, we
should consider what immediate losses might be irreparable and
avoid actions that produce them. A nuclear winter would
obviously be an unacceptable short-term cost. An increase in
the vociferous complaining about America on Arab TV, however,
can be expected and tolerated.
Some short-term costs
deserve extensive discussion, informed by the concerns of
diplomats, economists, lawyers, and others, before they are
accepted or rejected. Psychiatrists have little to contribute
to these proceedings other than to point out that the
criterion for judging a policy is clear: If terrorist behavior
continues, then--given that each successful attack makes
subsequent attacks more likely--efforts to stop it should be
enhanced, even though short-term losses will increase.
When we prevail in stopping terrorist behavior, we
will likely discover much support for us in the oppressed
Muslim world, support now hidden by the clamor for war. We can
be sure that most Muslim mothers and fathers do not want their
children lured to violent deaths in the name of some wild,
overvalued idea promoted by charismatic tyrants whose own sons
never get sent on suicide missions. Freedom will be welcomed
once the majority can speak openly. We already see this in
Afghanistan. The short-term losses of the bombing phase have
been overcome by the joy of long-term release from the
Taliban.
In sum, a realistic, pragmatic psychiatric
depiction of terrorism--one that avoids dubious theories about
meaning, as well as wishful thinking about how to manage
it--can dispel confusion and offer a context for the
understandings contributed by other disciplines. Thus, the
proposals advanced here about managing terrorism fit with the
idea of proceeding with a just war.
This approach
allows us to assure our critics that, even as we know
short-term losses to be inevitable when behavior must be
changed, we also presume that many of the losses will be
repaired by the long-term gains of success. All can agree that
force and destruction are not enough for a sustained peace.
Eventually we must repair some of what is damaged and develop
our understanding of the grievances and concerns of our
adversaries. To any who doubt our capacity to use more than
force to gain a long-term peace, we can offer the historical
instances of American magnanimity and devoted efforts at
rebuilding where we had conquered, as after the Civil War and
the two world wars of the 20th century.
We are a
forgiving people, but now, at the start of the first war of
the 21st century, is the time for action--action directed by a
coherent view of our adversaries and of what they are trying
to do to us. Churchill defined these matters better than any
psychiatrist. "Our aim," he said, ". . . is victory, victory
at all costs, victory in spite of all terror, victory, however
long and hard the road may be; for without victory, there is
no survival."
Paul R. McHugh is University
Distinguished Service Professor of Psychiatry and Behavioral
Science at the Johns Hopkins School of Medicine and former
psychiatrist-in-chief of the Johns Hopkins Hospital.
|