Secession, the State, and the Immigration
Problem
by Hans-Hermann
Hoppe
I
Human
cooperation is the result of three factors. First, the fact of
differences among men and/or the geographical distribution of
nature-given factors of production. Second, the fact of higher
productivity achieved under the division of labor based on the
mutual recognition of private property (the exclusive control of
every man over his own body and his physical appropriations and
possessions) as compared to either self-sufficient isolation or
aggression, plunder and domination. And third, the human ability to
recognize this latter fact. But for the higher productivity of labor
performed under divison of labor and the human ability to recognize
this fact, explains Ludwig von Mises, "men would have forever
remained deadly foes of one another, irreconcilable rivals in their
endeavors to secure a portion of the scarce supply of means of
sustenance provided by nature. Each man would have been forced to
view all other men as his enemies; his craving for the satisfaction
of his own appetites would have brought him into an implacable
conflict with all his neighbors. No sympathy could possibly develop
under such a state of affairs." [Human
Action, 144]
The higher productivity achieved under the division of labor
and the human ability to recognize this fact explains the origin of
the most elementary and fundamental of human institutions: the
family and the family household. Second, it explains the fact of
neighborhood (community) among homogeneous people (families, clans,
tribes): of neighborhood in the form of adjacent properties owned by
separate and equal owners and neighborhood in the unequal form of
the relationship characteristic of a father and his son, a landlord
and his tenant, or a community founder and his follower-residents.
Third and most important for our purposes, it explains the
possibility of the peaceful coexistence of heterogeneous and alien
communities. Even if the members of different communities find each
other physically and/or behaviorally strange, irritating, annoying
or worse, and do not want to associate as neighbors, they may still
engage in mutually beneficial trade if they are spatially separated
from each other.
Let me clarify this picture and assume the existence of
different races, ethnicities, languages, religions, and cultures
(henceforth summarily: ethno-cultures). Based on the just mentioned
insight that "likes" associate with other likes and live spatially
separated from "unlikes," the following picture emerges: People of
one ethno-culture tend to live in closer proximity to one another
and spatially separated and distant from people of another
ethno-culture. Whites live among Whites and separate from Asians and
Blacks. Italian speakers live among other Italians and separate from
English speakers. Christians live among other Christians and
separate from Muslims. Catholics live among Catholics and separate
from Protestants, etc. Naturally, some "overlap" and "mixing" of
different ethno-cultures in various "border-territories" exists.
Moreover, as centers of interregional trade, cities naturally
display a higher degree of ethno-cultural heterogeneity. This not
withstanding, however, every neighborhood and community is
internally homogeneous (uni-cultural). In fact, even in border
territories and cities the spatial association and separation of
likes and unlikes to be found in the macrocosm finds its microcosmic
equivalent. Nothing like a society where members of different
ethno-cultures live as neighbors or in close physical proximity to
each other (as propagated by some American multiculturalists) will
emerge. Rather, the emerging multiculturalism is one in which many
distinctly different ethno-cultures coexist in physical-spatial
separation and distant from one another, and trade with each other
from afar.
Let us take one more step and assume that all property is
owned privately and the entire globe is settled. Every piece of
land, every house and building, every road, river, and lake, every
forest and mountain, and all of the coastline is owned by private
owners or firms. No such thing as "public" property or "open
frontier" exists. And let us take a look at the problem of migration
under this scenario of a "natural order."
First and foremost, there is no such thing as "freedom of
migration" in a natural order. People cannot move about as they
please. Wherever a person moves, he moves on private property; and
private ownership implies the owner’s right to include as well as to
exclude others from his property. Essentially, a person can move
only if he is invited by a recipient property owner, and this
recipient-owner can revoke his invitation and expel his invitees
whenever he deems their continued presence on his property
undesirable (in violation of his visitation code).
There will be plenty of movement under this scenario, because
there are powerful reasons to include: to open access to one’s
property; but there are also reasons to exclude: to restrict or
close access. Those who are the most inclusive are the owners of
roads, railway stations, harbors, and airports, for example.
Interregional movement is their business. Accordingly, their
admission standards can be expected to be low, typically requiring
no more than the payment of a user fee. However, even they would not
follow a completely non-discriminatory admission policy. For
instance, they would exclude intoxicated or unruly people, beggars,
and bums from their property, and they may videotape or otherwise
monitor or screen their customers while on their
property.
The situation for the owners of retail establishments,
hotels, and restaurants is similar. They are in the business of
selling and renting and thus offer easy access to their property.
They have every economic incentive not to discriminate
unfairly against "strangers" or "foreigners," because this would
lead to reduced profits, or losses. However, they must be
significantly more circumspect and restrictive in their admission
policy than the owners of roads or airports. They must take into
account the local-domestic repercussions that the presence of
strangers may have. If local-domestic sales suffer due to a
retailer’s or hotel’s open admission policy vis-a-vis foreigners,
then discrimination is economically justified. In order to
overcome this possible problem, then, commercial establishments can
be expected to require of their "foreign" visitors at a minimum
adherence to local standards of conduct and appearance.
The situation is similar for local employers. They prefer
lower to higher wage rates; hence, they are not predisposed against
foreigners. However, they must be sensitive to the repercussions on
the local labor force that may result from the employment of
foreigners; that is, they must be fearful of the possibility that an
ethno-culturally heterogeneous work force might lead to lower
productivity. Moreover, employment requires housing, and it is in
the residential housing and real estate market where discrimination
against and exclusion of ethno-cultural strangers will tend to be
most pronounced. For it is in the area of residential as
contrasted to commercial property where the human desire to be
private, secluded and protected and undisturbed from external events
and intrusions, is most pronounced. The value of residential
property to its owner depends essentially on its almost total
exclusivity. Only family members, and occasionally friends, are
included. And if residential property is located in a neighborhood,
this desire for undisturbed possession – peace and privacy – is best
accomplished by a high degree of ethno-cultural homogeneity (as this
lowers transaction costs while simultaneously increasing protection
from external disturbances and intrusions). In renting or selling
residential property to strangers (and especially to strangers from
ethno-culturally distant quarters) heterogeneity is introduced into
the neighborhood. Transaction costs tend to increase, and the
peculiar peace-and-privacy-security – the freedom from external,
foreign intrusions – sought and expected of residential property
tends to fall, resulting in lower residential property
values.
Under the scenario of a natural order, then, it can be
expected that there will be plenty of interregional trade and
travel. But owing to the natural discrimination against
ethno-cultural strangers in the area of residential housing and real
estate there will be little actual migration, i.e., permanent
resettlement. And whatever little migration there is, it will be by
individuals who are more or less completely assimilated to their
newly adopted community and its ethno-culture.
II
Let me now introduce the institution of a State.
The definition of a State assumed here is rather
uncontroversial: A State is an agency which possesses an exclusive
monopoly of ultimate decision-making and conflict arbitration within
a given territory. In particular, a State can insist that all
conflicts involving itself be adjudicated by itself or its agents.
And implied in the power to exclude all others from acting as
ultimate judge, as the second defining element of a State, is its
power to tax: to unilaterally determine the price justice seekers
must pay to the State for its services as the monopolistic provider
of law and order.
Certainly, based on this definition it is easy to understand
why there might be a desire to establish a State. Not, as we are
told in kindergarten, in order to attain the "common good" or
because there would be no order without a State, but for a reason
far more selfish and base. For he who is a monopolist of final
arbitration within a given territory can make and
create laws in his own favor rather than recognize and apply
existing law; and he who can legislate can also tax and thus enrich
himself at the expense of impoverishing others.
I cannot cover here the fascinating question of how such an
extraordinary institution as a State with the power to legislate and
tax can possibly arise, except to note that ideologies and
intellectuals have a lot to do with it. Rather, I will assume states
as "given" (as in fact they are) and consider the changes as regards
migration that result from their existence.
First, with the establishment of a state and territorially
defined state borders, "immigration" takes on an entirely new
meaning. In a natural order, immigration is a person’s migration
from one neighborhood-community into a different one
(micro-migration). In contrast, under statist conditions immigration
is immigration by "foreigners" from across state borders, and the
decision whom to exclude or include, and under what conditions,
rests not with a multitude of independent private property owners or
neighborhoods of owners, but with a single central (and
centralizing) state-government as the ultimate sovereign of all
domestic residents and regarding all of their properties
(macro-migration). Now, if a domestic resident-owner invites a
person and arranges for his access onto his property but the
government excludes this person from the state territory, this is a
case of forced exclusion (a phenomenon that does not exist in
a natural order). On the other hand, if the government admits a
person while there is no domestic resident-owner who has invited
this person onto his property, this is a case of forced
integration (also non-existent in a natural order, where all
movement is invited).
III
In order to comprehend the significance of this change from
decentralized admission by a multitude of property owners and
owner-associations (micro-migration) to centralized admission by a
state (macro-migration), and in particular in order to grasp the
potentialities of forced integration under statist conditions, it is
necessary first to briefly consider a state’s policy of
domestic migration. Based on the state’s definition as a
territorial monopolist of legislation and taxation and the
assumption of "self-interest," the basic features of its policy can
be predicted.
Most fundamentally, it can be predicted that the state’s
agents will be interested in increasing (maximizing) tax revenues
and/or expanding the range of legislative interference with
established private property rights, but they will have little or no
interest in actually doing what a state is supposed to do:
protecting private property owners and their property from domestic
and foreign invasion.
More specifically, because taxes and legislative interference
with private property rights are not paid and accepted voluntarily
but are met with resistance, a state, to assure its own power to tax
and legislate, must have an existential interest in providing its
agents access to everyone and all property within the state’s
territory. In order to accomplish this, a state must take control of
(expropriate) all existing private roads and then use its tax
revenue to construct more and additional "public" roads, places,
parks and lands, ultimately until everyone’s private property
borders onto or is encircled by public lands and roads.
Many economists have argued that the existence of public
roads indicates an imperfection of the natural – free market –
order. According to them, the free market "under-produces" the
so-called "public" good of roads; and tax-funded public roads
rectify this deficiency and enhance overall economic efficiency (by
facilitating interregional movement and trade and lowering
transaction costs). Obviously, this is a somewhat starry-eyed view
of things.
Free markets do produce roads, although they may well
produce less and different roads than under statist conditions. And
as viewed from the perspective of a natural order, the increased
production of roads under statist conditions represents not an
improvement but an "over-production" or better yet "mal-production"
of roads. Public roads are not simply innocent and harmless
facilitators of interregional exchange. First and foremost they are
facilitators of state taxation and control. On public roads the
government’s taxmen, police, and military can proceed directly to
everyone’s doorstep.
In addition, public roads and lands lead to a distortion and
artificial break-up of the spatial association and separation
characteristic of a natural order. As explained, there are reasons
to be close and inclusive, but there are also reasons to be
physically distant and separated from others. The over-production of
roads occurring under statist conditions means on the one hand that
different communities are brought into greater proximity to one
another than they would have preferred (on grounds of demonstrated
preference). On the other hand, it means that one coherent community
is broken up and divided by public roads.
Moreover, under the particular assumption of a
democratic state even more specific predictions can be made.
Almost by definition, a state’s territory extends over several
ethno-culturally heterogeneous communities, and dependent on
recurring popular elections, a state-government will predictably
engage in redistributive policies. In an ethno-culturally mixed
territory this means playing one race, tribe, linguistic or
religious group against another; one class within anyone of these
groups against another (the rich vs. the poor, the capitalists vs.
the workers, etc.); and finally, mothers against fathers and
children against parents. The resulting income and wealth
redistribution is complex and varied. There are simple transfer
payments from one group to another, for instance. However,
redistribution also has a spatial aspect. In the realm of spatial
relations it finds expression in an ever more pervasive network of
non-disciminatory "affirmative action" policies imposed on private
property owners.
An owner’s right to exclude others from his property is the
means by which he can avoid "bads" from happening: events that will
lower the value of his property to him. By means of an unceasing
flood of redistributive legislation, the democratic state has worked
relentlessly not only to strip its citizens of all arms (weapons)
but also to strip domestic property owners of their right of
exclusion, thereby robbing them of much of their personal and
physical protection. Commercial property owners such as stores,
hotels, and restaurants are no longer free to exclude or restrict
access as they see fit. Employers can no longer hire or fire who
they wish. In the housing market, landlords are no longer free to
exclude unwanted tenants. Furthermore, restrictive covenants are
compelled to accept members and actions in violation of their very
own rules and regulations. In short, forced integration is
ubiquitous, making all aspects of life increasingly
unpleasant.
IV
Before this backdrop of domestic state policies we can return
to the problem of immigration under statist conditions. It is now
clear what state admission implies. It does not merely imply
centralized admission. By admitting someone onto its territory, the
state also permits this person to proceed on public roads and lands
to every domestic resident’s doorsteps, to make use of all public
facilities and services (such as hospitals and schools), and to
access, protected by a multitude of non-discrimination laws, every
commercial establishment, employment, and residential housing.
Only one more element is missing in my reconstruction. Why
would immigration ever be a problem for a state? Who would
want to migrate from a natural order into a statist area? A statist
area would tend to lose its residents, especially its most
productive subjects. It would be an attraction only for potential
state-welfare recipients (whose admission would only further
strengthen the emigration tendency). If anything, there is an
emigration problem for a state. In fact, the institution of a
state is a cause of emigration; and indeed, it is the most
important or even the sole cause of mass migrations (more
powerful and devastating in its effects than any hurricane,
earthquake or flood).
What has been missing in our reconstruction is the assumption
of a multitude of states partitioning the entire globe (the absence
of natural orders anywhere). Then, as one state causes mass
emigration, another state will be confronted with the problem of
mass immigration; and the general direction of mass migration
movements will be from territories where states exploit
(legislatively expropriate and tax) their subjects more (and wealth
accordingly tends to be lower) to territories where states exploit
less (and wealth is higher).
We have finally arrived in the present, when the Western
world – Western Europe, North America, and Australia – is faced with
the specter of state-caused mass immigration from all over the rest
of the world. What is being – and what can be – done about this
situation?
Out of sheer self-interest states will not put up no defense
at all against uninvited intruders (that is: declare an "open
border" policy). Otherwise, the influx of immigrants would quickly
assume such proportions that the domestic state-welfare system would
collapse (apart from other problems such as popular resistance and
unrest). On the other hand, the Western welfare states do not
prevent tens or even hundreds of thousands (and in the case of the
United States well in excess of a million) of uninvited foreigners
per year from entering and settling their territories. Moreover, as
far as legal (rather than tolerated illegal) immigration is
concerned, the Western welfare states have adopted a
non-discriminatory "affirmative action" admission policy. That is,
they set a maximum immigration target and then allot quotas to
various emigration countries or regions, irrespective of how
ethno-culturally similar or dissimilar such places and regions of
origin are, thus further aggravating the problem of forced
integration.
In light of the unpopularity of this policy, one might wonder
about the motive for engaging in it. However, given the nature of
the state it is not difficult to discover such a rationale. States,
as will be recalled, are also promoters of forced domestic
integration. Forced integration is a means of breaking up all
intermediate social institutions and hierarchies (in between the
state and the individual) such as family, clan, tribe, community,
and church and their internal layers and ranks of authority. In so
doing the individual is isolated (atomized) and its power of
resistance vis-a-vis the state weakened. In the "logic" of the
state, a good dose of foreign invasion, especially if it comes from
strange and far-away places, is reckoned to further strengthen this
tendency. And the present situation offers a particularly opportune
time to do so, for in accordance with the inherently centralizing
tendency of states and statism generally and promoted here and now
in particular by the U.S. as the world’s only remaining superpower,
the Western world – or more precisely the
neoconservative-socialdemocratic elites controlling the state
governments in the U.S. and Western Europe – is committed to the
establishment of supra-national states (such as the European Union)
and ultimately one world state. National, regional or communal
attachments are the main stumbling block on the way toward this
goal. A good measure of uninvited foreigners and government imposed
multiculturalism is calculated to further weaken and ultimately
destroy national, regional, and communal identities and thus promote
the goal of a One World Order, led by the U.S., and a new "universal
man."
V
What if anything can be done to spoil these statist designs
and regain security and protection from invasion, whether foreign or
domestic?
Let me begin with a proposal made by the editors of the
Wall Street Journal, the Cato Institute, and various
left-libertarian writers of an "open" or "no" border policy – not
because this proposal has any merit. To the contrary, it helps to
bring out clearly what the problem is and what needs to be done to
solve it.
It is not difficult to predict the consequences of an open
border policy in the present world. If Switzerland, Austria, Germany
or Italy, for instance, freely admitted everyone who made it to
their borders and demanded entry, these countries would quickly be
overrun by millions of third-world immigrants from Albania,
Bangladesh, India, Nigeria, for example. As the more perceptive
open-border advocates realize, the domestic state-welfare programs
and provisions would collapse as a consequence. This would not be a
reason for concern; for surely, in order to regain effective
protection of person and property, the welfare state must be
abolished. But then comes the great leap – or the gaping hole – in
the open border argument. Somehow, out of the ruins of the
democratic welfare states, we are supposed to believe, a new natural
order will emerge.
The first error involved in this line of reasoning can be
readily identified. Once the welfare states have collapsed under
their own weight, the masses of immigrants who have brought this
about are still there. They have not been miraculously transformed
into Swiss, Austrians, Bavarians or Lombards, but remain what they
are: Zulus, Hindus, Ibos, Albanians, or Bangladeshis. Assimilation
can work when the number of immigrants is small. It is entirely
impossible, however, if immigration occurs on a mass scale. In that
case, immigrants will simply transport their own ethno-culture onto
the new territory. Accordingly, when the welfare state has imploded
there will be a multitude of "little" (or not so little) Calcuttas,
Daccas, Lagos’, and Tiranas strewn all over Switzerland, Austria and
Italy. It betrays a breathtaking sociological naivitee to believe
that out of this admixture a natural order will emerge. Based on all
historical experience with such forms of multiculturalism, and given
the existence of a state that intrudes into every aspect of social
and economic life, it can safely be predicted instead that the
result will be civil war. There will be wide-spread plundering and
squattering leading to massive capital consumption, and civilization
as we know it would disappear from Switzerland, Austria and Italy.
Furthermore, the host population will quickly be outbred and
ultimately physically displaced by their "guests." There will be
still Alps in Austria and Switzerland, but no Austrians or
Swiss.
However, the error of the open border proposal goes further
than its dire consequences. The fundamental error of the proposal is
moral or ethical in nature and lies in its assumption. It is the
underlying assumption that foreigners are "entitled," or have a
"right," to immigrate. In fact, they have no such right
whatsoever.
Foreigners would have a right to enter Switzerland, Austria
or Italy only if these places were uninhabited (unowned)
territories. However, they are owned, and no one has a right
to enter territories owned by others (unless invited by the owner).
Nor is it permissible to argue, as some open border proponents have
done, that while foreigners may not enter private property
without the owner’s permission they may do so with public
property. In their eyes, public property is akin to unowned property
and thus "open" to everyone, domestic citizen and foreigners alike.
But this analogy between public property and unowned resources is
mistaken. There exists a categorical difference between unowned
resources (open frontier) and public property. Public property is
the result of state-government confiscations – of legislative
expropriations and/or taxation – of originally privately owned
property. While the state does not recognize anyone as its
private owner, all of government controlled public property has in
fact been brought about by the tax-paying members of the domestic
public. Austrians, Swiss, and Italians, in accordance with the
amount of taxes paid by each citizen, have funded the Austrian,
Swiss, and Italian public property. Hence, they must be considered
its legitimate owners. Foreigners have not been subject to domestic
taxation and expropriation; hence, they cannot be assumed to have
any rights regarding Austrian, Swiss or Italian public
property.
The recognition of the moral status of public property as
expropriated private property is not only sufficient grounds for
rejecting the open border proposal. It is equally important for
combatting the present semi-open "affirmative action" immigration
policies of the Western welfare states.
Until now, in the debate on immigration policy too much
emphasis has been placed on consequentialist (utilitarian)
arguments. Apologists of the status quo have argued that most
immigrants become productive and work and hence immigration
contributes to rising domestic standards of living. Against this
critics have argued that the existing state-welfare institutions and
provisions increasingly invite welfare-immigration, and they have
warned that the only advantage of the current policies over the open
border alternative is that the former will take decades until
leading ultimately to similarly dire effects as the latter will
produce within years. As important as the resolution of these issues
is, however, it is not decisive. The opposition against current
immigration policies is ultimately independent of whether
immigration will make per capita GDP (or similar statistical
measures) rise or fall. It is a matter of justice: of right and
wrong.
Understandably the democratic welfare states try to conceal
the source of public property (i.e., acts of expropriation).
However, they do acknowledge that public property is "somehow" the
property of the citizens and they are their citizens’ trustees in
regard to public property. Indeed, the state’s legitimacy is
derived from its claim to protect its citizens and their property
from invaders, intruders, and trespassers domestic and foreign.
Regarding foreigners, this would require that the state act like the
gatekeepers in private gated communities: to check every newcomer
for an invitation and monitor his movement on route toward his final
destination. When it is pointed out and made clear that, contrary to
this, the government instead tolerates or even promotes the
intrusion and invasion of masses of aliens who by no stretch of the
imagination can be deemed welcome or invited by domestic residents,
this is or may become a threat to a government’s legitimacy and
exert enough pressure for it to adopt a more restrictive and
discriminatory admission policy.
But this can only be the beginning, for even if public
opinion induced the state to adopt an immigration stance more in
accordance with popular sentiments and justice, this would not
change the fact that the interests of private property owners and
those of the state as a territorial monopolist of legislation and
taxation are incompatible and in permanent conflict with each other.
A state is a contradiction in terms: a property protector who may
expropriate the property of the protected through legislation and
taxation. Predictably, a state will be interested in maximizing tax
revenues and power (the range of legislative interference with
private property rights) but disinterested in protecting anything
except itself. What we experience in the area of immigration is only
one aspect of a general problem. States are also supposed to protect
their citizen from domestic intrusions and invasions; yet as we have
seen they actually disarm them, encircle them, tax them, and strip
them of their right to exclusion, thus rendering them
helpless.
Accordingly, the solution to the immigration problem is at
the same time the solution to the general problem inherent in the
institution of a state and public property. It involves the return
to a natural order by means of secession. To regain security from
domestic and foreign intrusion and invasion, the central nation
states will have to be decomposed into their constituent parts. The
Austrian and the Italian central state do not own Austrian and
Italian public property. Supposedly, they are its citizens’
trustees. But they do not protect them and their property. Hence,
just as the Austrians and the Italians (and not foreigners) are the
owners of Austria and Italy, so by extension of the same principle
do the Carinthians and the Lombards (in accordance with individual
tax payments) own Carinthia and Lombardy, and the Bergamese Bergamo
(and not the Viennese and the Roman government). By means of
secession, the central state’s public roads and lands are
repossessed by their genuine owners: provinces, cities, towns,
villages, neighborhoods, and ultimately private property owners and
ownership associations. The central state, stripped of its public
property, has no longer access and its laws no longer apply
anywhere. At the same time, the right to exclusion inherent in
private property and essential for personal security and protection
is returned into the hands of a multitude of independent private
decisionmaking units.
May 16, 2001
Hans-Hermann Hoppe [send
him mail] is Professor of Economics at the University of Nevada
Las Vegas, Las Vegas, Nevada, Senior Fellow of the Ludwig von Mises
Institute, Auburn, Alabama, and Editor of the Journal of Libertarian
Studies, An Interdisciplinary Quarterly Review. He is the
author of Kritik
der kausalwissenschaftlichen Sozialforschung (1983),
Eigentum, Anarchie und Staat (1987), A Theory
of Socialism and Capitalism (1989), The
Economics and Ethics of Private Property (1993), and Democracy:
The God That Failed (forthcoming). In Italian, see Abasso
la democrazia. L’etica libertaria e la crisi dello stato
(Leonardo Facco Editore, 2000). For additional information see:
www.mises.org/faculty.
Copyright 2001 by Hans-Hermann
Hoppe |